You can only save one who do you choose Doug MacKay

You are the captain of the Mallory 7,
an interstellar cargo transport.

On your way to the New Lindley spaceport,
you receive a distress call.

There’s been an explosion
on the Telic 12

and its passengers are running
out of oxygen.

As you set a course to intercept,
you check the Telic 12′s manifest.

It’s currently transporting
30 middle-aged individuals

from some of Earth’s poorest districts
to the labor center on New Lindley,

where they’ll be assigned
jobs on the spaceport.

But as you approach the Telic 12,
you receive a second distress call.

A luxury space cruiser called
the Pareto has lost a thruster,

sending them careening
towards an asteroid belt.

Without your help, the 20 college students
headed for vacation

aboard the Pareto are all doomed.

So with only enough time to save one ship,
which one should you choose?

This dilemma is an example of a broader
class of problems

where a life-saving resource—
such as a donated organ or vaccine—

is scarce.

There are many schools of thought
on how to approach these problems,

and one of the most influential
is utilitarianism,

an ethical view first systematically
developed

by Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill.

In this view,
you should choose the action

which promises the greatest
sum of happiness.

Though, how to define and measure
happiness is a difficult question.

For example, hedonists would suggest
a happy life

contains the most pleasure
and the least pain.

Others might say it’s the life
where your desires are most fulfilled.

However happiness is defined,

most would agree that saving 30 lives
has the potential

to generate more happiness than saving 20.

But is it enough to consider
how many lives would be saved?

Or should you also consider how many
life years would be?

Assuming a life expectancy of 80,
saving the lives of the students,

with an average age of 20,
saves 1,200 life years,

while saving the workers,
with an average age of 45, saves 1,050.

All things being equal,
a longer life should promise

a greater sum of happiness
than a shorter one.

So perhaps saving the smaller ship
actually has the potential

to generate the most happiness.

If all these calculations feel a bit cold,

you may want to consider
a different approach.

The philosopher Derek Parfit argues
we should give priority to the worse off,

since benefits to those groups
matter more

than equivalent benefits to the well-off.

In this view, it’s more urgent to help
those whose basic needs aren’t met

even if they’re harder to help
than those who are flourishing.

But often, determining which group is
truly worse off can get complicated fast.

In our case, Earth is still beset
by drastic inequalities

in wealth and opportunity.

And those able to afford
a vacation on New Lindley

and transport on a luxury cruiser

are no doubt among the most well-off
people on the planet.

The workers, by contrast,
are among the most disadvantaged,

traveling away from home for months
at a time to perform service work.

With fewer resources and opportunities,

it’s likely they’ve experienced more
hardship in their lives

than the vacationers,

so maybe they’re more deserving of rescue?

On the other hand, the students have
experienced less life overall—

so perhaps they’re worse off?

Or maybe none of these variables
should influence our decision.

The philosopher John Taurek famously
argued that in these types of cases,

the numbers don’t count.

Each person is deserving
of equal concern and respect,

so the best way to decide which passengers
to save is to flip a coin.

While this might seem arbitrary at first,
this approach treats all parties equally,

giving each individual
an equal chance of being rescued.

Could any passenger argue that they’re
being treated unfairly by a coin flip?

It’s tough to say.

But how they— and you— feel about the
result may be another dilemma altogether.

你是
星际货物运输机 Mallory 7 的船长。

在前往新林德利太空港的途中,
您收到了求救信号。

Telic 12 发生爆炸

,乘客
氧气不足。

当你设定一个拦截路线时,
你检查了 Telic 12 的清单。

它目前正在将
30 名中年人

从地球上一些最贫困的地区运送
到新林德利的劳工中心,

在那里他们将被分配
到太空港的工作。

但当您接近 Telic 12 时,
您会收到第二个求救信号。

一艘名为帕累托的豪华太空巡洋舰
失去了一个推进器,

将它们
推向小行星带。

没有你的帮助,
前往

帕累托号上度假的 20 名大学生注定要完蛋。

所以只有足够的时间来拯救一艘船,
你应该选择哪一艘?

这种困境是更
广泛的问题

的一个例子,其中拯救生命的资源——
例如捐赠的器官或疫苗——

是稀缺的。

关于如何解决这些问题有许多学派

,其中最有影响力的
一种是功利主义,

这是一种

由杰里米·边沁和约翰·斯图尔特·米尔首先系统发展的伦理观点。

在这种观点下,
你应该选择能

带来最大
幸福的行动。

然而,如何定义和衡量
幸福是一个难题。

例如,享乐主义者会
建议幸福的生活

包含最多的快乐
和最少的痛苦。

其他人可能会说,这
是最能满足你欲望的生活。

不管幸福是如何定义的,

大多数人都会同意拯救 30 条生命

比拯救 20 条生命更有可能产生更多幸福。

但是考虑
将拯救多少条生命就足够了吗?

或者你还应该考虑多少
生命年?

假设预期寿命为 80

岁,挽救平均年龄为 20 岁的学生的生命,可
挽救 1,200 生命年,

而挽救
平均年龄为 45 岁的工人,可挽救 1,050 生命年。

在所有条件相同的情况下
,较长的寿命应该比较短的寿命

带来更多的幸福

所以也许拯救较小的船
实际上有

可能产生最大的幸福。

如果所有这些计算都感觉有点冷,

您可能需要考虑
一种不同的方法。

哲学家德里克·帕菲特(Derek Parfit)认为,
我们应该优先考虑

贫困人口,因为这些群体的

利益比富裕者的同等利益更重要。

在这种观点看来,帮助
那些基本需求得不到满足的人,

即使他们
比那些蓬勃发展的人更难帮助,也更为紧迫。

但通常,确定哪个群体的情况
确实更糟会很快变得复杂。

就我们而言,地球仍然

财富和机会方面的严重不平等所困扰。

那些有
能力在新林德利度假

并乘坐豪华巡洋舰的

人无疑是这个星球上最富裕的
人之一。

相比之下,工人
是最弱势的群体,

他们
一次要离开家几个月才能从事服务工作。

由于资源和机会较少,

他们的生活可能比度假者经历更多的
困难

所以也许他们更值得救援?

另一方面,学生们
总体上经历的生活更少——

所以也许他们的情况更糟?

或者也许这些变量
都不应该影响我们的决定。

哲学家约翰·陶雷克(John Taurek)著名地
辩称,在这些类型的案例中

,数字不算数。

每个人都
值得同等关注和尊重,

因此决定要拯救哪些乘客的最佳方法
是掷硬币。

虽然起初这似乎是武断的,但
这种方法平等对待所有各方,

让每个人
都有平等的获救机会。

任何乘客都可以争辩说他们
受到了抛硬币的不公平对待吗?

很难说。

但他们——以及你——对
结果的看法可能完全是另一个困境。