Would you sacrifice one person to save five Eleanor Nelsen

Imagine you’re watching a runaway trolley
barreling down the tracks

straight towards five workers
who can’t escape.

You happen to be standing next to a switch

that will divert the trolley
onto a second track.

Here’s the problem.

That track has a worker on it, too,
but just one.

What do you do?

Do you sacrifice one person to save five?

This is the trolley problem,

a version of an ethical dilemma that
philosopher Philippa Foot devised in 1967.

It’s popular because it forces us
to think about how to choose

when there are no good choices.

Do we pick the action
with the best outcome

or stick to a moral code that prohibits
causing someone’s death?

In one survey, about 90% of respondents
said that it’s okay to flip the switch,

letting one worker die to save five,

and other studies, including a virtual
reality simulation of the dilemma,

have found similar results.

These judgments are consistent with the
philosophical principle of utilitarianism

which argues that
the morally correct decision

is the one that maximizes well-being
for the greatest number of people.

The five lives outweigh one,

even if achieving that outcome requires
condemning someone to death.

But people don’t always take
the utilitarian view,

which we can see by changing
the trolley problem a bit.

This time, you’re standing on a bridge
over the track

as the runaway trolley approaches.

Now there’s no second track,

but there is a very large man
on the bridge next to you.

If you push him over,
his body will stop the trolley,

saving the five workers,

but he’ll die.

To utilitarians,
the decision is exactly the same,

lose one life to save five.

But in this case, only about 10% of people

say that it’s OK to throw the man
onto the tracks.

Our instincts tell us that deliberately
causing someone’s death

is different than allowing them to die
as collateral damage.

It just feels wrong for reasons
that are hard to explain.

This intersection between ethics
and psychology

is what’s so interesting
about the trolley problem.

The dilemma in its many variations reveal
that what we think is right or wrong

depends on factors other than
a logical weighing of the pros and cons.

For example, men are more likely
than women

to say it’s okay to push the man
over the bridge.

So are people who watch a comedy clip
before doing the thought experiment.

And in one virtual reality study,

people were more willing
to sacrifice men than women.

Researchers have studied
the brain activity

of people thinking through the classic
and bridge versions.

Both scenarios activate areas of the brain
involved in conscious decision-making

and emotional responses.

But in the bridge version,
the emotional response is much stronger.

So is activity in an area of the brain

associated with processing
internal conflict.

Why the difference?

One explanation is that pushing someone
to their death feels more personal,

activating an emotional aversion
to killing another person,

but we feel conflicted because we know
it’s still the logical choice.

“Trolleyology” has been criticized by some
philosophers and psychologists.

They argue that it doesn’t reveal anything
because its premise is so unrealistic

that study participants
don’t take it seriously.

But new technology is making this kind
of ethical analysis

more important than ever.

For example, driver-less cars
may have to handle choices

like causing a small accident
to prevent a larger one.

Meanwhile, governments are researching
autonomous military drones

that could wind up making decisions of
whether they’ll risk civilian casualties

to attack a high-value target.

If we want these actions to be ethical,

we have to decide in advance
how to value human life

and judge the greater good.

So researchers who study
autonomous systems

are collaborating with philosophers

to address the complex problem
of programming ethics into machines,

which goes to show that
even hypothetical dilemmas

can wind up on a collision course
with the real world.

想象一下,您正在看着一辆失控的
手推车沿着轨道

直奔五名
无法逃脱的工人。

你碰巧站在一个开关旁边,该开关

会将手推车转移
到第二条轨道上。

这就是问题所在。

那条轨道上也有一个工人,
但只有一个。

你做什么工作?

你会牺牲一个人来拯救五个人吗?

这就是电车问题,

哲学家菲利帕·富特(Philippa Foot)在 1967 年设计的道德困境的一个版本。

它很受欢迎,因为它迫使我们

在没有好的选择时思考如何选择。

我们是选择
结果最好的行动,

还是坚持禁止导致某人死亡的道德准则

在一项调查中,大约 90% 的受访者
表示可以翻转开关,

让一名工人死去救五个人,

而其他研究,包括
对困境的虚拟现实模拟,

也发现了类似的结果。

这些判断与
功利主义的哲学原则是一致的,功利主义

认为道德上正确的决定

是为最多的人带来最大福祉的决定

五命重于一命,

即使实现这一结果需要
判处某人死刑。

但人们并不总是
采取功利主义的观点

,我们可以通过
稍微改变手推车问题来看到这一点。

这一次,当失控的电车接近时,你站在轨道上的一座桥上

现在没有第二条轨道了,

但是在你旁边的桥上有一个非常大的人

如果你把他推倒,
他的身体会停下手推车,

拯救五个工人,

但他会死。

对功利主义者来说
,决定完全一样,

丧一命救五命。

但在这种情况下,只有大约 10% 的人

表示可以将人
扔到铁轨上。

我们的直觉告诉我们,故意
造成

某人死亡与让他们
作为附带损害而死亡是不同的。

由于难以解释的原因,它只是感觉不对

伦理学和心理学的交叉点


电车问题的有趣之处。

其许多变体中的困境表明
,我们认为是对还是错

取决于除
对利弊进行逻辑权衡之外的因素。

例如,男人
比女人

更有可能说可以把
男人推过桥。 在进行思想实验之前

观看喜剧片段的人也是如此

在一项虚拟现实研究中,

人们
比女性更愿意牺牲男性。

研究

人员通过经典
和桥梁版本研究了人们思考的大脑活动。

这两种情况都会激活大脑中
参与有意识决策

和情绪反应的区域。

但在桥牌版本中
,情绪反应要强烈得多。 与处理内部冲突

相关的大脑区域的活动也是如此

为什么有区别?

一种解释是,将某人
推向死亡感觉更加个人化,

激发了
对杀死另一个人的情绪厌恶,

但我们感到矛盾,因为我们知道
这仍然是合乎逻辑的选择。

“电车学”一直受到一些
哲学家和心理学家的批评。

他们认为它没有透露任何信息,
因为它的前提是如此不切实际

,以至于研究参与者
没有认真对待它。

但新技术使
这种伦理分析

比以往任何时候都更加重要。

例如,无人驾驶汽车
可能不得不处理

诸如引发小事故
以防止更大事故的选择。

与此同时,政府正在研究
自主军用

无人机,最终可以决定
它们是否会冒着平民伤亡的风险

来攻击高价值目标。

如果我们希望这些行为合乎道德,

我们必须提前决定
如何珍视人类生命

并判断更大的利益。

因此,研究
自治系统的研究人员

正在与哲学家合作,

解决将
伦理编程到机器中的复杂问题,

这表明
即使是假设的困境

也可能最终
与现实世界发生冲突。