Do we see reality as it is Donald Hoffman

I love a great mystery,

and I’m fascinated by the greatest
unsolved mystery in science,

perhaps because it’s personal.

It’s about who we are,

and I can’t help but be curious.

The mystery is this:

What is the relationship
between your brain

and your conscious experiences,

such as your experience
of the taste of chocolate

or the feeling of velvet?

Now, this mystery is not new.

In 1868, Thomas Huxley wrote,

“How it is that anything so remarkable
as a state of consciousness comes about

as the result of irritating nervous tissue

is just as unaccountable

as the appearance of the genie
when Aladdin rubbed his lamp.”

Now, Huxley knew that brain activity

and conscious experiences are correlated,

but he didn’t know why.

To the science of his day,
it was a mystery.

In the years since Huxley,

science has learned a lot
about brain activity,

but the relationship
between brain activity

and conscious experiences
is still a mystery.

Why? Why have we made so little progress?

Well, some experts think
that we can’t solve this problem

because we lack the necessary
concepts and intelligence.

We don’t expect monkeys to solve
problems in quantum mechanics,

and as it happens, we can’t expect
our species to solve this problem either.

Well, I disagree. I’m more optimistic.

I think we’ve simply
made a false assumption.

Once we fix it, we just
might solve this problem.

Today, I’d like tell you
what that assumption is,

why it’s false, and how to fix it.

Let’s begin with a question:

Do we see reality as it is?

I open my eyes

and I have an experience that I describe
as a red tomato a meter away.

As a result, I come to believe
that in reality,

there’s a red tomato a meter away.

I then close my eyes, and my experience
changes to a gray field,

but is it still the case that in reality,
there’s a red tomato a meter away?

I think so, but could I be wrong?

Could I be misinterpreting
the nature of my perceptions?

We have misinterpreted
our perceptions before.

We used to think the Earth is flat,
because it looks that way.

Pythagorus discovered that we were wrong.

Then we thought that the Earth
is the unmoving center of the Universe,

again because it looks that way.

Copernicus and Galileo discovered,
again, that we were wrong.

Galileo then wondered if we might
be misinterpreting our experiences

in other ways.

He wrote: “I think that tastes,
odors, colors, and so on

reside in consciousness.

Hence if the living creature were removed,
all these qualities would be annihilated.”

Now, that’s a stunning claim.

Could Galileo be right?

Could we really be misinterpreting
our experiences that badly?

What does modern science
have to say about this?

Well, neuroscientists tell us
that about a third of the brain’s cortex

is engaged in vision.

When you simply open your eyes
and look about this room,

billions of neurons
and trillions of synapses are engaged.

Now, this is a bit surprising,

because to the extent that
we think about vision at all,

we think of it as like a camera.

It just takes a picture
of objective reality as it is.

Now, there is a part of vision
that’s like a camera:

the eye has a lens that focuses
an image on the back of the eye

where there are 130 million
photoreceptors,

so the eye is like a 130-megapixel camera.

But that doesn’t explain
the billions of neurons

and trillions of synapses
that are engaged in vision.

What are these neurons up to?

Well, neuroscientists tell us
that they are creating, in real time,

all the shapes, objects, colors,
and motions that we see.

It feels like we’re just taking a snapshot
of this room the way it is,

but in fact, we’re constructing
everything that we see.

We don’t construct
the whole world at once.

We construct what we need in the moment.

Now, there are many demonstrations
that are quite compelling

that we construct what we see.

I’ll just show you two.

In this example, you see some red discs
with bits cut out of them,

but if I just rotate
the disks a little bit,

suddenly, you see a 3D cube
pop out of the screen.

Now, the screen of course is flat,

so the three-dimensional cube
that you’re experiencing

must be your construction.

In this next example,

you see glowing blue bars
with pretty sharp edges

moving across a field of dots.

In fact, no dots move.

All I’m doing from frame to frame
is changing the colors of dots

from blue to black or black to blue.

But when I do this quickly,

your visual system creates
the glowing blue bars

with the sharp edges and the motion.

There are many more examples,
but these are just two

that you construct what you see.

But neuroscientists go further.

They say that we reconstruct reality.

So, when I have an experience
that I describe as a red tomato,

that experience is actually
an accurate reconstruction

of the properties of a real red tomato

that would exist
even if I weren’t looking.

Now, why would neuroscientists
say that we don’t just construct,

we reconstruct?

Well, the standard argument given

is usually an evolutionary one.

Those of our ancestors
who saw more accurately

had a competitive advantage compared
to those who saw less accurately,

and therefore they were more likely
to pass on their genes.

We are the offspring of those
who saw more accurately,

and so we can be confident that,
in the normal case,

our perceptions are accurate.

You see this in the standard textbooks.

One textbook says, for example,

“Evolutionarily speaking,

vision is useful precisely
because it is so accurate.”

So the idea is that accurate perceptions
are fitter perceptions.

They give you a survival advantage.

Now, is this correct?

Is this the right interpretation
of evolutionary theory?

Well, let’s first look at a couple
of examples in nature.

The Australian jewel beetle

is dimpled, glossy and brown.

The female is flightless.

The male flies, looking,
of course, for a hot female.

When he finds one, he alights and mates.

There’s another species in the outback,

Homo sapiens.

The male of this species
has a massive brain

that he uses to hunt for cold beer.

(Laughter)

And when he finds one, he drains it,

and sometimes throws the bottle
into the outback.

Now, as it happens, these bottles
are dimpled, glossy,

and just the right shade of brown
to tickle the fancy of these beetles.

The males swarm all over
the bottles trying to mate.

They lose all interest
in the real females.

Classic case of the male
leaving the female for the bottle.

(Laughter) (Applause)

The species almost went extinct.

Australia had to change its bottles
to save its beetles.

(Laughter)

Now, the males had successfully
found females for thousands,

perhaps millions of years.

It looked like they saw reality
as it is, but apparently not.

Evolution had given them a hack.

A female is anything dimpled,
glossy and brown,

the bigger the better.

(Laughter)

Even when crawling all over the bottle,
the male couldn’t discover his mistake.

Now, you might say, beetles, sure,
they’re very simple creatures,

but surely not mammals.

Mammals don’t rely on tricks.

Well, I won’t dwell on this,
but you get the idea. (Laughter)

So this raises an important
technical question:

Does natural selection really favor
seeing reality as it is?

Fortunately, we don’t have
to wave our hands and guess;

evolution is a mathematically
precise theory.

We can use the equations of evolution
to check this out.

We can have various organisms
in artificial worlds compete

and see which survive and which thrive,

which sensory systems are more fit.

A key notion in those
equations is fitness.

Consider this steak:

What does this steak do
for the fitness of an animal?

Well, for a hungry lion looking to eat,
it enhances fitness.

For a well-fed lion looking to mate,
it doesn’t enhance fitness.

And for a rabbit in any state,
it doesn’t enhance fitness,

so fitness does depend
on reality as it is, yes,

but also on the organism,
its state and its action.

Fitness is not the same thing
as reality as it is,

and it’s fitness,
and not reality as it is,

that figures centrally
in the equations of evolution.

So, in my lab,

we have run hundreds of thousands
of evolutionary game simulations

with lots of different
randomly chosen worlds

and organisms that compete
for resources in those worlds.

Some of the organisms
see all of the reality,

others see just part of the reality,

and some see none of the reality,

only fitness.

Who wins?

Well, I hate to break it to you,
but perception of reality goes extinct.

In almost every simulation,

organisms that see none of reality

but are just tuned to fitness

drive to extinction all the organisms
that perceive reality as it is.

So the bottom line is, evolution
does not favor veridical,

or accurate perceptions.

Those perceptions of reality go extinct.

Now, this is a bit stunning.

How can it be that not seeing
the world accurately

gives us a survival advantage?

That is a bit counterintuitive.

But remember the jewel beetle.

The jewel beetle survived
for thousands, perhaps millions of years,

using simple tricks and hacks.

What the equations
of evolution are telling us

is that all organisms, including us,
are in the same boat as the jewel beetle.

We do not see reality as it is.

We’re shaped with tricks
and hacks that keep us alive.

Still,

we need some help with our intuitions.

How can not perceiving
reality as it is be useful?

Well, fortunately, we have
a very helpful metaphor:

the desktop interface on your computer.

Consider that blue icon
for a TED Talk that you’re writing.

Now, the icon is blue and rectangular

and in the lower right corner
of the desktop.

Does that mean that the text file itself
in the computer is blue,

rectangular, and in the lower
right-hand corner of the computer?

Of course not.

Anyone who thought that misinterprets
the purpose of the interface.

It’s not there to show you
the reality of the computer.

In fact, it’s there to hide that reality.

You don’t want to know about the diodes

and resistors and all
the megabytes of software.

If you had to deal with that,
you could never write your text file

or edit your photo.

So the idea is that evolution
has given us an interface

that hides reality and guides
adaptive behavior.

Space and time, as you
perceive them right now,

are your desktop.

Physical objects are simply icons
in that desktop.

There’s an obvious objection.

Hoffman, if you think that train
coming down the track at 200 MPH

is just an icon of your desktop,

why don’t you step in front of it?

And after you’re gone,
and your theory with you,

we’ll know that there’s more
to that train than just an icon.

Well, I wouldn’t step
in front of that train

for the same reason

that I wouldn’t carelessly drag
that icon to the trash can:

not because I take the icon literally –

the file is not literally blue
or rectangular –

but I do take it seriously.

I could lose weeks of work.

Similarly, evolution has shaped us

with perceptual symbols
that are designed to keep us alive.

We’d better take them seriously.

If you see a snake, don’t pick it up.

If you see a cliff, don’t jump off.

They’re designed to keep us safe,
and we should take them seriously.

That does not mean that we
should take them literally.

That’s a logical error.

Another objection: There’s
nothing really new here.

Physicists have told us for a long time
that the metal of that train looks solid

but really it’s mostly empty space
with microscopic particles zipping around.

There’s nothing new here.

Well, not exactly.

It’s like saying, I know that
that blue icon on the desktop

is not the reality of the computer,

but if I pull out my trusty
magnifying glass and look really closely,

I see little pixels,

and that’s the reality of the computer.

Well, not really – you’re still
on the desktop, and that’s the point.

Those microscopic particles
are still in space and time:

they’re still in the user interface.

So I’m saying something far more radical
than those physicists.

Finally, you might object,

look, we all see the train,

therefore none of us constructs the train.

But remember this example.

In this example, we all see a cube,

but the screen is flat,

so the cube that you see
is the cube that you construct.

We all see a cube

because we all, each one of us,
constructs the cube that we see.

The same is true of the train.

We all see a train because
we each see the train that we construct,

and the same is true
of all physical objects.

We’re inclined to think that perception
is like a window on reality as it is.

The theory of evolution is telling us
that this is an incorrect interpretation

of our perceptions.

Instead, reality is more like a 3D desktop

that’s designed to hide
the complexity of the real world

and guide adaptive behavior.

Space as you perceive it is your desktop.

Physical objects are just
the icons in that desktop.

We used to think that the Earth is flat
because it looks that way.

Then we thought that the Earth
is the unmoving center of reality

because it looks that way.

We were wrong.

We had misinterpreted our perceptions.

Now we believe that spacetime and objects

are the nature of reality as it is.

The theory of evolution is telling us
that once again, we’re wrong.

We’re misinterpreting the content
of our perceptual experiences.

There’s something that exists
when you don’t look,

but it’s not spacetime
and physical objects.

It’s as hard for us to let go
of spacetime and objects

as it is for the jewel beetle
to let go of its bottle.

Why? Because we’re blind
to our own blindnesses.

But we have an advantage
over the jewel beetle:

our science and technology.

By peering through the lens of a telescope

we discovered that the Earth
is not the unmoving center of reality,

and by peering through the lens
of the theory of evolution

we discovered that spacetime and objects

are not the nature of reality.

When I have a perceptual experience
that I describe as a red tomato,

I am interacting with reality,

but that reality is not a red tomato
and is nothing like a red tomato.

Similarly, when I have an experience
that I describe as a lion or a steak,

I’m interacting with reality,

but that reality is not a lion or a steak.

And here’s the kicker:

When I have a perceptual experience
that I describe as a brain, or neurons,

I am interacting with reality,

but that reality is not a brain or neurons

and is nothing like a brain or neurons.

And that reality, whatever it is,

is the real source of cause and effect

in the world – not brains, not neurons.

Brains and neurons
have no causal powers.

They cause none of our
perceptual experiences,

and none of our behavior.

Brains and neurons are a species-specific
set of symbols, a hack.

What does this mean
for the mystery of consciousness?

Well, it opens up new possibilities.

For instance,

perhaps reality is some vast machine
that causes our conscious experiences.

I doubt this, but it’s worth exploring.

Perhaps reality is some vast,
interacting network of conscious agents,

simple and complex, that cause
each other’s conscious experiences.

Actually, this isn’t as crazy
an idea as it seems,

and I’m currently exploring it.

But here’s the point:

Once we let go of our massively intuitive

but massively false assumption
about the nature of reality,

it opens up new ways to think
about life’s greatest mystery.

I bet that reality will end up
turning out to be more fascinating

and unexpected than we’ve ever imagined.

The theory of evolution presents us
with the ultimate dare:

Dare to recognize that perception
is not about seeing truth,

it’s about having kids.

And by the way, even this TED
is just in your head.

Thank you very much.

(Applause)

Chris Anderson: If that’s
really you there, thank you.

So there’s so much from this.

I mean, first of all, some people
may just be profoundly depressed

at the thought that,
if evolution does not favor reality,

I mean, doesn’t that to some extent
undermine all our endeavors here,

all our ability to think
that we can think the truth,

possibly even including
your own theory, if you go there?

Donald Hoffman: Well, this does not
stop us from a successful science.

What we have is one theory
that turned out to be false,

that perception is like reality
and reality is like our perceptions.

That theory turns out to be false.

Okay, throw that theory away.

That doesn’t stop us from now postulating
all sorts of other theories

about the nature of reality,

so it’s actually progress to recognize
that one of our theories was false.

So science continues as normal.
There’s no problem here.

CA: So you think it’s possible
– (Laughter) –

This is cool, but what you’re saying
I think is it’s possible that evolution

can still get you to reason.

DH: Yes. Now that’s a very,
very good point.

The evolutionary game simulations that I
showed were specifically about perception,

and they do show that our perceptions
have been shaped

not to show us reality as it is,

but that does not mean the same thing
about our logic or mathematics.

We haven’t done these simulations,
but my bet is that we’ll find

that there are some selection pressures
for our logic and our mathematics

to be at least in the direction of truth.

I mean, if you’re like me,
math and logic is not easy.

We don’t get it all right, but at least
the selection pressures are not

uniformly away from true math and logic.

So I think that we’ll find that we have
to look at each cognitive faculty

one at a time and see
what evolution does to it.

What’s true about perception may not
be true about math and logic.

CA: I mean, really what you’re proposing
is a kind of modern-day Bishop Berkeley

interpretation of the world:

consciousness causes matter,
not the other way around.

DH: Well, it’s slightly
different than Berkeley.

Berkeley thought that, he was a deist,
and he thought that the ultimate

nature of reality is God
and so forth,

and I don’t need to go
where Berkeley’s going,

so it’s quite a bit
different from Berkeley.

I call this conscious realism.
It’s actually a very different approach.

CA: Don, I could literally talk with you
for hours, and I hope to do that.

Thanks so much for that.
DH: Thank you. (Applause)

我喜欢一个伟大的谜

,我
对科学中最大的未解之谜着迷,

也许是因为它是个人的。

这是关于我们是谁

,我不禁好奇。

谜团是这样的:

你的大脑

和你的意识体验之间有什么关系,

比如你
对巧克力味道的体验

或天鹅绒的感觉?

现在,这个谜并不新鲜。

1868 年,托马斯·赫胥黎写道:

“像阿拉丁擦灯时出现的精灵一样,由于刺激了神经组织而出现了像意识状态这样显着的事情,这是怎么回事

?”

现在,赫胥黎知道大脑活动

和意识体验是相关的,

但他不知道为什么。

对他那个时代的科学来说,
这是一个谜。

在赫胥黎之后的这些年里,

科学已经了解了很多
关于大脑活动的知识,


大脑活动

和意识体验
之间的关系仍然是一个谜。

为什么? 为什么我们进展如此缓慢?

那么,一些专家
认为我们无法解决这个问题,

因为我们缺乏必要的
概念和智慧。

我们不指望猴子
解决量子力学中的问题,

而且碰巧,我们也不能指望
我们的物种解决这个问题。

好吧,我不同意。 我比较乐观。

我认为我们只是
做了一个错误的假设。

一旦我们修复它,我们
可能会解决这个问题。

今天,我想告诉
你这个假设是什么,

为什么它是错误的,以及如何解决它。

让我们从一个问题开始

:我们是否看到了现实的本来面目?

我睁开眼睛

,我有一种体验,我将其描述
为一米外的红番茄。

结果,我开始相信
,在现实中,

一米外有一个红番茄。

然后我闭上眼睛,我的体验
变成了一片灰色的田野,

但现实中,
一米外还有一颗红番茄吗?

我想是的,但我会错吗?

我会不会误解
了我的感知的本质?

我们以前误解
了我们的看法。

我们曾经认为地球是平的,
因为它看起来是那样的。

毕达哥拉斯发现我们错了。

然后我们认为地球
是宇宙不动的中心

,因为它看起来是那样的。

哥白尼和伽利略
再次发现我们错了。

伽利略然后想知道我们是否
会以其他方式误解我们的经验

他写道:“我认为味道、
气味、颜色等

存在于意识中。

因此,如果生物被移除,
所有这些品质都会被消灭。”

现在,这是一个惊人的主张。

伽利略会是对的吗?

我们真的会
如此严重地误解我们的经历吗?

现代科学
对此有什么看法?

好吧,神经科学家告诉我们
,大约三分之一的

大脑皮层与视觉有关。

当你睁开
眼睛环顾这个房间时,

数十亿个神经元
和数万亿个突触都在参与其中。

现在,这有点令人惊讶,

因为就
我们考虑视觉的程度而言,

我们认为它就像一台相机。

它只是
照原样拍摄客观现实的照片。

现在,视觉的一部分
就像一个相机

:眼睛有一个镜头,可以
将图像聚焦在眼睛后部,

那里有 1.3 亿个
感光器,

所以眼睛就像一个 130 兆像素的相机。

但这并不能
解释参与视觉的数十亿神经元

和数万亿突触

这些神经元在做什么?

好吧,神经科学家告诉我们
,他们正在实时创造我们看到的

所有形状、物体、颜色
和运动。

感觉就像我们只是按原样拍摄
这个房间的快照,

但实际上,我们正在
构建我们所看到的一切。

我们不会
一下子构建整个世界。

我们在当下构建我们需要的东西。

现在,有许多
演示非常引人注目

,我们构建了我们所看到的。

我只给你看两个。

在这个例子中,你会看到一些红色的圆盘
,上面切掉了一些小块,

但如果我
稍微旋转一下圆盘

,你会突然看到一个 3D 立方体
从屏幕中弹出。

现在,屏幕当然是平面的,

所以你正在体验的 3D 立方体

一定是你的构造。

在下一个示例中,

您会看到
带有非常锐利边缘的发光蓝色条

在点场上移动。

事实上,没有点移动。

我从一帧到另一帧所做的
只是将点的颜色

从蓝色变为黑色或黑色变为蓝色。

但是当我快速执行此操作时,

您的视觉系统会创建

带有锐利边缘和运动的发光蓝色条。

还有更多示例,
但这

只是您构建所见的两个示例。

但神经科学家走得更远。

他们说我们重建现实。

所以,当我有一种
我描述为红番茄的

体验时,这种体验实际上

对真实红番茄特性的准确重建,

即使我没有看,它也会存在。

现在,为什么神经科学家会
说我们不只是构建,

我们重建?

好吧,给出的标准论点

通常是进化论的。 与视力

较差的祖先相比
,视力较准确

的祖先具有竞争优势

,因此他们更有
可能传递自己的基因。

我们是
那些看得更准确的人的后代

,因此我们可以确信,
在正常情况下,

我们的感知是准确的。

您可以在标准教科书中看到这一点。

例如,一本教科书说:

“从进化上讲,

视觉之所以有用,正是
因为它非常准确。”

所以这个想法是准确的感知
是更合适的感知。

他们给你一个生存优势。

现在,这是正确的吗?

这是对进化论的正确解释
吗?

好吧,让我们首先看几个
自然界中的例子。

澳大利亚宝石甲虫

有酒窝,有光泽,呈棕色。

雌性不会飞。

雄性苍蝇
,当然,寻找一个性感的雌性。

当他找到一个时,他会下车并交配。

内陆还有另一种物种,

智人。

这个物种的雄性
有一个巨大的大脑

,他用它来寻找冰镇啤酒。

(笑声

) 当他找到一个时,他会把它倒掉

,有时还会把瓶子
扔到内陆。

现在,碰巧的是,这些瓶子
有酒窝,有光泽

,恰到好处的棕色色调
可以满足这些甲虫的喜好。

雄性
蜂拥而至,试图交配。

他们
对真正的女性失去了所有兴趣。

男性
离开女性为瓶子的经典案例。

(笑声)(掌声)

这个物种几乎灭绝了。

澳大利亚不得不更换瓶子
来拯救它的甲虫。

(笑声)

现在,男性已经成功地
找到了女性数千年,

也许是数百万年。

看起来他们看到了现实
,但显然不是。

进化给了他们一个黑客。

女性是任何有酒窝、
有光泽和棕色的东西

,越大越好。

(笑声)

即使在瓶子上爬来爬去
,雄性也无法发现自己的错误。

现在,你可能会说,甲虫,当然,
它们是非常简单的生物,

但肯定不是哺乳动物。

哺乳动物不依赖技巧。

好吧,我不会详述这一点,
但你明白了。 (笑声)

所以这就提出了一个重要的
技术问题:

自然选择真的有利于
看到现实的本来面目吗?

幸运的是,
我们不必挥手猜测;

进化论是一个数学上
精确的理论。

我们可以使用进化方程
来检验这一点。

我们可以让
人造世界中的各种有机体相互竞争

,看看哪些能存活,哪些能茁壮成长,

哪些感觉系统更适合。

这些
方程中的一个关键概念是适应度。

考虑一下这块牛排:

这块牛排
对动物的健康有什么作用?

好吧,对于一只饥饿的狮子来说,
它可以增强体质。

对于一只想要交配的吃得好的狮子来说,
它不会增强体质。

对于处于任何状态的兔子来说,
它不会增强适应性,

因此适应性确实
取决于现实,是的,

但也取决于有机体、
它的状态和它的行为。

适应度
与现实不同,

它是适应度,
而不是现实本身,是

进化方程的核心。

因此,在我的实验室中,

我们运行了数十万
次进化游戏模拟,

其中包含许多不同的
随机选择的世界


在这些世界中争夺资源的生物。

一些有机体
看到了所有的现实,

另一些只看到了现实的一部分,

还有一些没有看到任何现实,

只有适应。

谁赢?

好吧,我不想告诉你,
但是对现实的感知已经消失了。

几乎在每一次模拟中,

没有看到任何现实

但只是调整到适应度

的生物会驱使所有
感知现实的生物灭绝。

所以底线是,进化
不支持真实的

或准确的感知。

那些对现实的看法消失了。

现在,这有点令人惊叹。

不能准确地看世界,怎么可能

给我们生存优势呢?

这有点违反直觉。

但请记住宝石甲虫。

宝石甲虫使用简单的技巧和技巧存活
了数千年,也许是数百

万年。

进化方程告诉我们的

是,包括我们在内的所有生物
都与宝石甲虫在同一条船上。

我们看不到现实的本来面目。

我们被塑造了
让我们活着的技巧和黑客。

尽管如此

,我们仍需要直觉方面的帮助。

怎么能不感知
现实,因为它是有用的?

好吧,幸运的是,我们有
一个非常有用的比喻:

计算机上的桌面界面。

考虑
一下您正在编写的 TED 演讲的蓝色图标。

现在,图标是蓝色的矩形


位于桌面的右下角。

这是否意味着计算机中的文本文件本身
是蓝色的,

矩形的,并且
位于计算机的右下角?

当然不是。

任何认为这样的人都会误解
界面的目的。

它不是为了向您展示
计算机的真实性。

事实上,它的存在是为了隐藏这个现实。

您不想了解二极管

和电阻器以及
所有兆字节的软件。

如果您必须处理这个问题,
您将永远无法编写文本文件

或编辑照片。

所以这个想法是
进化给了我们

一个隐藏现实并指导
适应性行为的界面。

正如您
现在所感知的,空间和时间

就是您的桌面。

物理对象只是
该桌面中的图标。

有明显的反对意见。

霍夫曼,如果您认为
以 200 英里/小时的速度驶下轨道的火车

只是您桌面的一个图标,您

为什么不走在它前面呢?

在你离开后
,你的理论与你同在,

我们会知道
这列火车不仅仅是一个图标。

好吧,我不会
踩到那辆火车前面,

原因

与我不会不小心将
那个图标拖到垃圾桶的原因相同:

不是因为我按字面理解图标

——文件不是字面上的蓝色
或矩形——

而是 我很认真地对待它。

我可能会失去数周的工作。

同样,进化


旨在让我们活着的感知符号塑造了我们。

我们最好认真对待他们。

如果你看到一条蛇,不要捡起它。

如果你看到悬崖,不要跳下。

它们旨在保护我们的安全
,我们应该认真对待它们。

这并不意味着我们
应该从字面上理解它们。

这是一个逻辑错误。

另一个反对意见:这里
没有什么新东西。

长期以来,物理学家一直告诉我们,
那辆火车的金属看起来很坚固,

但实际上它大部分是空旷的空间
,周围有微小的粒子飞驰而过。

这里没有什么新鲜事。

嗯,不完全是。

这就像说,我知道
桌面上的那个蓝色图标

不是电脑的现实,

但如果我拿出我信赖的
放大镜仔细观察,

我会看到一些小像素

,这就是电脑的现实。

嗯,不是真的——你
还在桌面上,这就是重点。

那些微观粒子
仍然存在于空间和时间中:

它们仍然存在于用户界面中。

所以我说的是比那些物理学家更激进的东西

最后,你可能会反对,

看,我们都看到了火车,

因此我们没有人建造火车。

但请记住这个例子。

在这个例子中,我们都看到了一个立方体,

但是屏幕是平的,

所以你
看到的立方体就是你构建的立方体。

我们都看到了一个立方体,

因为我们每个人都
构建了我们所看到的立方体。

火车也是如此。

我们都看到了火车,因为
我们每个人都看到了我们建造的火车,

所有物理对象也是如此。

我们倾向于认为
感知就像是现实的一扇窗户。

进化论告诉我们
,这是

对我们感知的错误解释。

相反,现实更像是一个 3D 桌面

,旨在隐藏
现实世界的复杂性

并引导自适应行为。

您认为的空间就是您的桌面。

物理对象只是
该桌面中的图标。

我们曾经认为地球是平的,
因为它看起来是那样的。

然后我们认为地球
是现实中不动的中心,

因为它看起来是那样的。

我们错了。

我们误解了我们的看法。

现在我们相信时空和物体

是现实的本质。

进化论再次告诉我们
,我们错了。

我们误解
了我们的知觉体验的内容。

当你不看时,有些东西存在,

但它不是时空
和物理对象。

我们很难
放开时空和物体,

就像宝石
甲虫放开它的瓶子一样。

为什么? 因为
我们对自己的盲目视而不见。

但我们
比宝石甲虫有一个优势:

我们的科学和技术。

通过望远镜的镜头

我们发现地球
不是现实的静止中心

,通过进化论的镜头

我们发现时空和物体

不是现实的本质。

当我有一种被
我描述为红番茄的感性体验时,

我正在与现实互动,

但现实不是红番茄
,也不像红番茄。

同样,当我有一种
我描述为狮子或牛排的体验时,

我正在与现实互动,

但那个现实不是狮子或牛排。

关键是:

当我有一种
我描述为大脑或神经元的感知体验时,

我正在与现实互动,

但现实不是大脑或神经元

,也与大脑或神经元完全不同。

而那个现实,不管它是什么,

都是世界上因果关系的真正来源

——不是大脑,也不是神经元。

大脑和神经元
没有因果关系。

它们不会引起我们的
知觉体验,

也不会引起我们的行为。

大脑和神经元是一组特定于物种
的符号,一种 hack。


对意识的奥秘意味着什么?

好吧,它开辟了新的可能性。

例如,

也许现实是某种巨大的机器
,它会导致我们有意识的体验。

我对此表示怀疑,但值得探索。

也许现实是一些
由有意识的代理组成的巨大的、相互作用的网络,

简单而复杂,它们会导致
彼此的有意识体验。

实际上,这并不像看起来那么疯狂

,我目前正在探索它。

但重点是:

一旦我们放弃对现实本质的大量直觉

但大量错误的假设

它就会开辟新的方式来
思考生命中最大的谜团。

我敢打赌,现实最终会变

得比我们想象的更迷人、更出人意料。

进化论向我们
展示了终极的勇气:

敢于承认感知
不是关于看到真相,

而是关于生孩子。

顺便说一句,即使是这个 TED
也只是在你的脑海中。

非常感谢你。

(掌声)

Chris Anderson:如果
真的有你在,谢谢。

所以有很多东西。

我的意思是,首先,有些人
可能会深感沮丧

,因为
如果进化不利于现实,

我的意思是,这不是在某种程度上
破坏了我们在这里的所有努力,

我们认为我们可以做到的所有能力 如果你去那里,
想想真相,

甚至可能包括
你自己的理论?

唐纳德·霍夫曼:嗯,这并不能
阻止我们取得成功的科学。

我们所拥有的是一种
被证明是错误的理论,

即感知就像现实,
而现实就像我们的感知一样。

事实证明,这个理论是错误的。

好吧,抛开这个理论。

这并不能阻止我们现在假设

关于现实本质的各种其他理论,

所以
承认我们的一个理论是错误的实际上是一个进步。

所以科学照常进行。
这里没有问题。

CA:所以你认为这是可能的
——(笑声)——

这很酷,但你说的是
我认为进化

仍然可以让你推理。

DH:是的。 现在这是一个非常
非常好的观点。

我展示的进化游戏模拟
是专门关于感知的

,它们确实表明我们的感知
已经被塑造成

不会向我们展示现实,

但这并不意味着
我们的逻辑或数学。

我们还没有进行这些模拟,
但我敢打赌,我们会发现

我们的逻辑和

数学至少要朝着真理的方向存在一些选择压力。

我的意思是,如果你像我一样,
数学和逻辑并不容易。

我们并不完全正确,但
至少选择压力并没有

完全偏离真正的数学和逻辑。

所以我认为我们会发现我们必须
一次只看一个认知能力


看看进化对它有什么影响。

对感知
正确的东西对数学和逻辑可能不是正确的。

CA:我的意思是,你真正提出的
是一种现代的伯克利主教

对世界的解释:

意识导致物质,
而不是相反。

DH:嗯,它
与伯克利略有不同。

伯克利认为,他是一个自然神论者
,他认为现实的终极

本质是上帝
等等

,我不需要去
伯克利去的地方,

所以它
和伯克利有很大的不同。

我称之为有意识的现实主义。
这实际上是一种非常不同的方法。

CA:唐,我真的可以和你聊
几个小时,我希望能那样做。

非常感谢。
DH:谢谢。 (掌声)