The paradox of value Akshita Agarwal

Imagine you’re on a game show,
and you can choose between two prizes:

a diamond

or a bottle of water.

It’s an easy choice.

The diamonds are clearly more valuable.

Now imagine being given
the same choice again,

only this time, you’re not on a game show,

but dehydrated in the desert
after wandering for days.

Do you choose differently?

Why? Aren’t diamonds still more valuable?

This is the paradox of value,

famously described
by pioneering economist Adam Smith.

And what it tells us is that defining
value is not as simple as it seems.

On the game show, you were thinking about
each item’s exchange value,

what you could obtain for them
at a later time,

but in an emergency,
like the desert scenario,

what matters far more is their use value,

how helpful they are
in your current situation.

And because we only get to choose
one of the options,

we also have to consider
its opportunity cost,

or what we lose by giving up
the other choice.

After all, it doesn’t matter how much
you could get from selling the diamond

if you never make it out of the desert.

Most modern economists deal with
the paradox of value

by attempting
to unify these considerations

under the concept of utility,

how well something satisfies
a person’s wants or needs.

Utility can apply to anything
from the basic need for food

to the pleasure of hearing
a favorite song,

and will naturally vary
for different people and circumstances.

A market economy provides us
with an easy way to track utility.

Put simply, the utility
something has to you

is reflected by how much you’d be
willing to pay for it.

Now, imagine yourself back in the desert,

only this time, you get offered
a new diamond or a fresh bottle of water

every five minutes.

If you’re like most people, you’ll first
choose enough water to last the trip,

and then as many diamonds
as you can carry.

This is because of something called
marginal utility,

and it means that when you choose
between diamonds and water,

you compare utility obtained
from every additional bottle of water

to every additional diamond.

And you do this each time
an offer is made.

The first bottle of water is worth more
to you than any amount of diamonds,

but eventually,
you have all the water you need.

After a while, every additional bottle
becomes a burden.

That’s when you begin to choose
diamonds over water.

And it’s not just necessities like water.

When it comes to most things,
the more of it you acquire,

the less useful or enjoyable
every additional bit becomes.

This is the law of diminishing
marginal utility.

You might gladly buy two or three
helpings of your favorite food,

but the fourth would
make you nauseated,

and the hundredth would spoil
before you could even get to it.

Or you could pay to see the same movie
over and over until you got bored of it

or spent all of your money.

Either way,
you’d eventually reach a point

where the marginal utility for buying
another movie ticket became zero.

Utility applies not just to buying things,
but to all our decisions.

And the intuitive way to maximize it
and avoid diminishing returns

is to vary the way we spend
our time and resources.

After our basic needs are met,

we’d theoretically decide
to invest in choices

only to the point they’re useful
or enjoyable.

Of course, how effectively any of us
manage to maximize utility in real life

is another matter.

But it helps to remember that the
ultimate source of value comes from us,

the needs we share,

the things we enjoy,

and the choices we make.

想象一下,您正在参加一个游戏节目
,您可以在两个奖品之间进行选择:

一颗钻石

或一瓶水。

这是一个简单的选择。

钻石显然更有价值。

现在想象一下
再次获得相同的选择,

只是这一次,你不是在参加游戏节目,

而是在沙漠
中流浪了几天后脱水了。

你选择不同吗?

为什么? 钻石不是更有价值吗?

这就是价值悖论,

著名
经济学家亚当·斯密曾描述过。

它告诉我们的是,定义
价值并不像看起来那么简单。

在游戏节目中,你考虑的是
每件物品的交换价值,

你以后可以为它们获得什么

但在紧急情况下,
比如沙漠场景

,更重要的是它们的使用价值,

它们
对你的帮助有多大 现在的情况。

而且因为我们只能选择
其中一个选项,

我们还必须考虑
它的机会成本,

或者我们放弃另一个选择会失去什么

毕竟,如果您永远无法走出沙漠,那么
您可以从出售钻石中获得多少收益并不重要

大多数现代经济学家

通过试图
将这些考虑统一

在效用的概念下来处理价值悖论

,即某物满足
一个人的需求的程度。

效用可以适用于
从对食物的基本需求


听到喜欢的歌曲的乐趣的任何事情,

并且自然会
因不同的人和环境而有所不同。

市场经济为我们
提供了一种追踪效用的简便方法。

简而言之,
某物对你

的效用反映在你
愿意为此付出多少。

现在,想象一下自己回到沙漠,

只是这一次,每五分钟你就会得到
一颗新钻石或一瓶新鲜水

如果你和大多数人一样,你会首先
选择足够的水来维持旅行,

然后尽可能多
地携带钻石。

这是因为所谓的
边际效用

,这意味着当您
在钻石和水之间进行选择时,

您会将
每增加一瓶水获得的效用

与每增加一颗钻石进行比较。

每次提出要约时,您都会这样做

对您而言,第一瓶水
比任何数量的钻石都更有价值,

但最终,
您将拥有所需的所有水。

一段时间后,每多喝一瓶
就成了负担。

那是您开始选择
钻石而不是水的时候。

它不仅仅是像水这样的必需品。

当涉及到大多数东西时,
你获得的东西越多,每一点额外

的东西就越没用或
变得越不愉快。

这就是
边际效用递减规律。

你可能很乐意买两到
三份你最喜欢的食物,

但第四份
会让你恶心,

而百分之一会
在你还没吃完之前就变质了。

或者你可以花钱一遍又一遍地看同一部电影
,直到你厌倦了

或者花光了所有的钱。

无论哪种方式,
您最终都会达到

购买
另一张电影票的边际效用为零的程度。

效用不仅适用于购买东西,
还适用于我们的所有决定。

最大化它并避免收益递减的直观方法

是改变我们花费
时间和资源的方式。

在我们的基本需求得到满足后,

理论上我们会
决定只投资

于它们有用
或令人愉快的选择。

当然,我们中的任何人如何有效
地在现实生活中最大限度地发挥效用

是另一回事。

但它有助于记住,
价值的最终来源来自我们、

我们分享的需求、

我们喜欢的事物

以及我们做出的选择。